This post first appeared at
The Nation.
Theology is morality is politics is law — and whether or not
it’s immediately obvious, the world is steeped in theology. In
contemporary America, and especially in the more secular
precincts of Western Europe, it seems unlikely that one could
look at a property deed or a government budget and find, just
beneath its explicit reasoning, traces of old theological
disputes and their resolutions. But they’re there, and examining
them offers a view of what might have been, had history — in
particular, the Protestant Reformation, ignited 500 years ago
this October by a German monk named Martin Luther — unfolded
differently.
Luther cuts a perplexing historical figure. In various
depictions, he is by turns fiery or meek, bombastic or shy,
licentious or pious, revolutionary or reactionary, cunning or
naively bewildered by what his high-minded remonstrance
unleashed on the world. In Erik Erikson’s famous study of the
early Luther, we find a young monk in the throes of an identity
crisis that would eventually hurl Europe into a similar one; in
Roland H. Bainton’s Here I Stand, we find Luther beset by
tumultuous bouts of desolation as well as stunning moments of
insight and clarity. Luther’s theology would place an emphasis
on spiritual simplicity, but his interior life was anything but
uncomplicated.
In Lyndal Roper’s new biography, Martin Luther: Renegade and
Prophet, he’s a charismatic, irascible German chauvinist with a
temper as quick as his wit, who is caught somewhat flat-footed
by the trajectory of the revolution he launched. Roper notes
that major fractures would begin to appear among Luther’s
followers less than a year after he defended himself at the Diet
of Worms in 1521; three years later, the Peasants’ War broke
out, a popular uprising fueled by the anti-authoritarian thrust
of Luther’s ideas, and one that wouldn’t be rivaled in size in
Europe until the French Revolution. Luther, Roper observes,
initially castigated both the rebellious peasants and their
feudal lords, but he eventually endorsed the cause of the
princes, declaring the rebels “mad dogs” up to “pure devil’s
work.” “With this stance,” Roper writes, “the social
conservatism of Luther’s Reformation became apparent.”
This paradox — that the Reformation could birth a peasant revolt
while its instigator rallied behind the princes — is a picture
of Protestantism’s confusing political legacy in miniature.
Protestantism arguably brought about many of the preconditions
for the Enlightenment and liberalism, and at the very least
introduced Europe to a headier skepticism of authority than had
prevailed before. (Indeed, Roper credits the Reformation with
sparking the secularization of the West.) On the other hand, the
release of significant portions of life — namely politics and
economics — from the purview of religious authority may have
expanded certain freedoms, but it didn’t result in a betterment
of conditions for the most disadvantaged, even as it helped
transform the Christian message into something far more internal
and private than that of the earlier church.
Reconciling the confusing, often paradoxical origins of
Protestantism in Luther and his successors seems like a good
project for a half-millennium retrospective. But if there is one
conclusion to be drawn from Roper’s book — as well as from two
other recent works, Alec Ryrie’s Protestants: The Faith That
Made the Modern World and John C. Rao’s anthology Luther and His
Progeny: 500 Years of Protestantism and Its Consequences for
Church, State and Society — it’s that Luther himself was more
catalyst than creator. Five centuries on, some Protestant sects
still bear the marks of his thought and personality, but others
seem barely touched by them at all. Every religion is fissile
and given to change, but the antinomian streak in Protestantism
makes it especially so, and the monumental role it imagined for
the individual conscience helps to explain, at least by Ryrie’s
lights, the origins of modern thought.
Martin Luther was born in 1483 and grew up in the small German
mining town of Mansfeld. “The son of a peasant,” by his own
account, Luther spent his childhood in Mansfeld’s muddy,
coal-dusted and pugilistic streets, which introduced him early
to the culture of vicious insults and brutal argumentation that
would later characterize — and help to popularize — many of his
famous polemics.
Luther’s story has been told many times, but Roper handles it
with special sensitivity, offering both an engrossing narrative
and capturing the ways in which Luther’s early life and
education contributed to the fixations that would occupy him in
his later years. After a dreary childhood in Mansfeld, the young
Luther set off to attend school in Magdeburg in 1497. He went on
to study at the University at Erfurt and entered law school
uneasily at his father’s behest.
It didn’t last. Luther instead was drawn to the church and took
vows as an Augustinian monk in 1505. He was particularly
attracted to the order’s learned friary and intellectual
tradition, and Augustine’s political theology — at least its
rhetorical shape — would go on to form an important dimension of
Luther’s own. In 1512, he received his doctorate in theology.
Now a thoroughly educated and opinionated man of God, Luther
began teaching theology at the University of Wittenberg, giving
sermons in the local church, and tallying the errors of his
peers and superiors.
By 1517, Luther had established himself as an accomplished, if
quarrelsome, preacher. He was known to have a particular (and
entirely reasonable) animus toward indul-gences, the means by
which certain church authorities parted faithful Catholics from
their money with theologically specious promises of salvation
and other favors. It was during one such dispute over the sale
of indulgences that Luther finally met his destiny, on the last
day of October 1517, at the doors of a Wittenberg church. There,
he posted his 95 theses disputing established Catholic teaching
— and launched a revolution that would transform the Christian
world.
Roper’s narrative adds rich detail to the story of Luther’s
youth and its impact on his later theological focus, and it
teases out the anxieties and doubts that plagued him even as he
pressed forward with the challenge that would become the
Protestant Reformation. Roper also diligently follows the ways
in which Luther frequently found himself at odds with the new
form of Christianity he had initiated, illuminating in moving
detail the relationships that crumbled around him as he became
less the reform-minded intellectual friar he once was and more
the influential defender of earthly princes.
Ryrie’s Protestants also tells us about Luther’s life, as well
as about many of the early Protestants who helped spread the
Reformation throughout Western Europe. But Ryrie also wants to
tell the story of how the Reformation transformed not just the
religious and political world but also our social and economic
one. A practicing pastor, Ryrie already knows well that it is
difficult, if not impossible, to speak of a single
Protestantism, and so he centers his book instead not on the
religion itself, but on its adherents and their shared, often
contentious history. This influence is hard to overstate,
especially for those of us in the United States, the even more
stridently Protestant offspring of Protestant England.
Ryrie’s central contention is that the Reformation changed the
ideological contours of Europe by toppling the traditional
sources of authority — indeed, the stability of any worldly
authority whatsoever. By so doing, it hastened (in some cases)
or precipitated (in others) the rise of modernity, a condition
that in Ryrie’s view is marked by a chronological era as well as
the spread of liberalism, secularism, democracy and capitalism.
Ryrie’s approach is historical and detailed; in his survey, he
moves from Luther’s beloved Germany to England and the Americas,
then to Asia and beyond. He devotes as much time to the
denominations of South Korea and China and the Pentecostal sweep
in Latin America as he does to Western mainline churches. He is
emphatic that Protestantism is more a family of widely varied
tendencies than a single, unified religion. Above all else,
Protestantism is, for Ryrie, a love affair with God, unmediated
by institutions.
Of course, love can find any number of expressions, and it’s the
particular shape of Luther’s love that helped define the
personality of Protestantism for centuries. As Roper tells us,
Luther’s “unbearable revulsion” — at his own sins, mainly, but
also those of others — was his “spiritual staple.” Feces and
bodily decay feature prominently in his sermons and
disputations, Roper notes, advancing a dim if not altogether
disgusted view of man before his Creator. Perpetually caught up
in a kind of spiritual anxiety, Luther was certain that there
was nothing humans could do to redeem themselves even remotely
in God’s eyes; instead, faith alone could provide one with the
opportunity to be saved. “One must give up on attempting to find
God through ‘the whore’ of reason,” Roper writes of Luther’s
theology, “for the point of faith is that it exceeds rationality
and reveals the distance between God and man.” For Luther, that
distance seems to have provided some comfort: While human
affairs are marked by filth and confusion, God reigns in remote
majesty, unsullied and glorious in perfect certitude, even as He
offers His sinful creatures a promise of the same.
This view of the gap between God and man helps explain Luther’s
allegiance to the German princes: His theology, from the start,
imbued worldly goings-on with far less spiritual significance
than the Catholic Church had, and it did so in order to make
Christianity a more “democratic” religion, one in which
individuals enjoy unmediated access to God. But Luther’s
Reformation didn’t simply undermine the church’s particularly
exploitative practices; it also envisioned a rift between heaven
and earth that, in Catholic thought, wasn’t nearly as wide or
intractable. The “inner man should have faith in God,” Roper
writes of Luther’s theology, “and we cannot arrive at faith
through works of the outer man.” Each person, then, is a kind of
self in a shell: One’s body is immersed in the profane and
mundane grind of daily life, but one’s innermost soul is
withdrawn and can be focused on heaven.
This distinction had immense consequences for how Christians in
Luther’s tradition would go on to engage the world around them.
For Luther, Ryrie writes, there was “an earthly kingdom: the
kingdom of secular politics, a place of law, justice and
punishment”; and then there was, “existing alongside it, and far
more important than it…the kingdom of heaven, whose only king is
Christ…. And this is where Christians’ hearts should be set, not
on the lumpen business of human politics.”
For Protestants, this represented an important remonstration
against the corruption and violence of various church-state
interactions, as well as a renewed image of God as the ruler of
a kingdom purer and better than the one we can experience
corporeally. It was an essentially spiritual call to arms
against the Vatican’s perceived materialism. But for many, the
rupture of heaven and earth also opened up a different vista:
that of secularism and of a world emptied of religious meaning.
Luther emphasized that human works made no difference to one’s
salvation; doing good was right, of course, but only God’s grace
— and one’s faith — could decide the destiny of one’s soul. This
liberated Christianity from some of its worldly constraints, but
it also meant coming to view the private and religious spheres
as divided from the public and secular ones.
The formation of a set of spheres separate from God’s purview
was perhaps an unexpected development for a faith desperate to
be closer to Him than the Catholic Church’s bulky intercession
would allow. And over the long history of that faith, many
Protestants haven’t seemed entirely convinced of the material
world’s separateness: When political events or institutions come
to be understood as obviously, egregiously wrong — slavery for
some Protestants, abortion for others, taxation for still others
— then the moral language concerning what God does or does not
want emerges. But this new mode of religious thinking also
helped open the door, Roper argues, to a new secular age: a
world in which church and state, conscience and politics,
remained separate on principle.
In a way, it takes a Catholic — or a set of Catholics, like
those that John C. Rao gathers in his anthology Luther and His
Progeny — to clarify just how transformative Protestantism was
in changing the modern world. By separating the political and
economic spheres from the realm of spiritual consideration,
Protestantism not only inaugurated our secular age; it also
helped — at least in the view of some of its critics — to give
the market free rein. As Brian McCall argues in his
contribution, while in the Catholic vision “economic works, as
well as any other type of works, will affect not only natural
but also supernatural ends,” the Protestant tradition proposed
that religion and morality remain realms distinct from that of
the economy.
This separation of economic considerations from spiritual ones
had its own political implications. “The Church and church
jurists,” McCall observes, “were intimately involved in the
development of economic laws that placed restraints on
individual economic freedom up to the eve of the Reformation.”
Thus, by disavowing those moral
constraints on the market, Protestant countries could reclaim a
sphere that was otherwise still shaped, to some extent, by the
Catholic Church from afar. But when the authority of the church
receded from this newly delineated political-economic sphere,
something else happened inadvertently: Contract and property
law, now released from adherence to religious law, shifted over
time, and a new social order began to develop throughout much of
the Western Hemisphere — especially in the English-speaking
North Atlantic. Protestantism did not create modern capitalism,
but it did clear a considerable amount of space for its
development.
“Protestant theology contributed to a shift in the underlying
basis of contract liability,” McCall writes, “shifting from
causa to consideration and promise to bargain.” Catholic jurists
had formerly required that the purpose of a contract be a just
and equitable one in order to enforce it, and they viewed breach
of contract more as an issue of breaking promises than of
failing to meet the substantive terms of the agreement. But
Protestant theology gave rise to the idea that contracts were
covenants, “which, although freely made, once entered into
[were] absolute.” Thus, by the middle of the 17th century,
Protestant courts had no obligation to try to bring about a
general moral good when they adjudicated cases on property and
contracts.
While much of the jurisprudence in Catholic countries relied on
a view of limited property rights that might allow their
societies to realize God’s intention for all of His creation to
be commonly held, the moral and legal thought in Protestant
countries more often argued that the best way to look after the
weak and needy was for each person to become as wealthy as
possible and then give freely of that wealth. As the
Enlightenment progressed, this vision blossomed into the liberal
tradition as we know it, and into an insistence on ever more
absolute property rights, sacrosanct from intrusion by church or
state (except, curiously, when the state enforced them), with
any means of redressing social or economic inequality primarily
beholden to a citizen’s own conscience.
Of course, in both strains of Christianity, human beings can
hardly be trusted with the careful stewardship of limited
resources — “The heart is deceitful above all things, and
desperately wicked,” says the Lord — but the Protestant theology
that followed from this period left little room for coercion by
church or state. Other factors besides Protestantism converged
to aid in the rise of liberal thought in the 18th century —
shifting economic possibilities, a burgeoning interest in the
sciences and the specter and reality of civil war, to name a few
— but at the root of it was a perspective of the world that
centered on the individual. “When no human power can direct or
absolve the conscience, it is the conscience that becomes the
true sovereign,” Ryrie writes, and the conscience, more often
than not, demands to be left to its own devices.
Where could the elevation of the individual conscience and the
bifurcation of holy pursuits from profane politics lead?
Enlightenment liberalism was not, and is not, capitalism; the
former is a collection of political, social and economic
theories, and the latter is a vast material system. Nor can (or
should) Protestantism, in all its variegated forms, be equated
with either liberalism or capitalism: There are expressly
anticapitalist and entirely illiberal Protestants, and no
tradition encompassing the Quakers, the Shakers and the Amish
could seriously be framed as a simple extension of liberalism.
Yet there appears to be an important connection between the
liberal thought that followed from Protestant arguments and the
emergence of capitalism. “The kind of sociopolitical structure
that Protestantism engenders — based on free inquiry,
participatory politics and limited government — tends to favor
market economics,” Ryrie argues, and “a certain generic
restlessness, an itchy instability, is absolutely a core
characteristic of the Protestant life.” As a result, he
explains, “this self-perpetuating dynamo of dissatisfaction and
yearning has helped to fuel and support the growth of
capitalism.”
It is hard to say what Luther himself would make of all this. In
her biography, Roper reminds us that “Luther was not ‘modern’”
and had no intention of ushering in a post-Christian era,
whether secular, liberal, democratic or capitalist. Not
coincidentally, Luther doesn’t appear to have been particularly
gifted at foreseeing how his ideas would transform politics or
would themselves be transformed by their emergence in public
life. His two-kingdoms theology “left him without a positive
account of what the state can do and how it might help its
citizens,” Roper writes, “and it did not allow for a situation
where a Christian or a Christian ruler would have to resist a
superior authority.” When such events arose in his lifetime,
Luther “abdicated responsibility, and left the matter for
jurists to decide.”
Nonetheless, the outcome of Luther’s revolution is visible in
our society today, where free markets and atomized individuals
are given primacy over whatever moral vision a religion or
ideology might attempt to impose on them. This wasn’t the intent
of the Reformation, and history is thick with Protestants
resisting modernity’s drift away from an interest in the common
good. Yet the way in which Ryrie divides his book makes the
ambiguous economic and political legacy of Protestantism all the
clearer. Act I concerns Protestantism versus Catholicism, with
the former in many respects successfully toppling the authority
and power of the latter. Act II is more like Protestantism
versus modernity, and modernity comes out on top — and not just
any kind of modernity, but the one specifically shaped by
capitalism’s rise. “The reality of a democratic age,” Ryrie
writes, “is that churches are answerable to the footloose
believers who fund them. Those who try to deny this fact are
swimming against the tide.”
The irony is that while Protestantism contributed some of the
ideological foundations for liberalism, it has also become
wedded to the logic that liberalism then fashioned into common
sense: If you don’t like something, simply take your money
elsewhere. Hence the prominence of the highly entrepreneurial
Christian right in America, and the relative weakness of the
Christian left: For the well-heeled, free-market Christianity —
which levels no rebuke at the rich and limits its moral
expectations to the sphere of the private and the personal — is
a much more compelling product than its older, less
laissez-faire counterpart.
But surely the true and honest message of Christ shouldn’t
blossom or wither based purely on the caprices of the moneyed
classes. And yet, if one does adhere to the radical centrality
of the individual’s conscience and to the relative uselessness
of earthly works, then how can he or she seek to upset the
social order? Ryrie’s expectations on that score are muted:
“Protestant political activism will certainly continue,” he
writes, but “few Protestants will have the stomach for forcing
their own moral disciplines onto entire societies…. Where they
do campaign for coercive legislation, they will do so on secular
grounds.” But if Protestantism insists on separating our
religious lives from our earthly ones, then does this mean the
powerful will be held to account for their actions only in the
afterlife? “Are Protestants, then, doomed simply to tag along
behind social shifts, finding justifications for them after the
fact?” Ryrie asks. “Very often, yes.”
Near the end of his book, Ryrie offers this uninspiring message.
But his history of Protestantism, like Roper’s biography of
Luther, also seems to offer an alternative set of possibilities.
Over and over again, Ryrie emphasizes that Protestantism is, at
heart, a love affair with God, as well as a radical rejection of
anything and everything that might come between lover and
beloved. Luther’s passion for God, in Roper’s retelling, also
appears as a romance. But love affairs are never static, so what
may have once been a requirement for loving God better on the
eve of the Reformation may no longer obtain now. Indeed, while
indulgences and vast networks of church authority once have
stood between the faithful and their love of God, it seems that
these days, the spheres created to separate our lives do much
the same, dividing the neediest among us from all that was
intended for them. There is no single resolution to this
circumstance, but understanding how we came to it helps us also
imagine a path forward. |